On November 12, 2005, Stephen Hawking gave a lecture in San
Francisco on the birth of the universe. I felt lucky to be in the audience.
Though not trained in physics or astronomy, I was eager to hear what Hawking had to say. Cosmology intrigued me, my curiosity having been sparked by
the likes of polymath Carl Sagan and science writer Nigel Calder, whose The Key to the Universe I’d found
fascinating and fathomable (it was a key, after all). About the Hawking event I
remember the lecture room, approximate size of the audience, disposition of the
chairs, where I sat and with whom, Hawking’s physical condition, Hawking’s
delivery, the duration of the talk, the reception afterwards, and a few
conversations I had with people at the reception. Of Hawking’s ideas, however, I
remember nothing.
What I recall about Hawking’s talk is the experience of
listening to Stephen Hawking. Embarkation was smooth, and the audience exhibited
high spirits. Hawking’s digitized voice may have disconcerted at first, but we
soon became habituated. I felt like a child who is learning to read, and sails
through the first simple sentences of her primer. Of the first 10% of Hawking’s
talk – call it the Prologue – I believe I understood every word. Beyond the Prologue,
however, I began to struggle. Again like a reader who has not attained fluency,
I had moments of successful decoding and comprehension, interspersed with
increasingly longer moments in which decoding failed, or failed to yield
comprehension. Struggle lasted through perhaps the next 15% of the talk. Struggle
at an end, for the next 10% of the talk I floundered. Brief flashes of apparent
comprehension were engulfed by waves of disorientation, confusion. Respite came
during the next 5% of the talk when knowledge of my limitations surfaced and I
recognized Truth: I was completely out of my depth. For the remaining 60% of Stephen
Hawking’s cosmology lecture, I was not decoding, I comprehended nothing, I was
no longer reading the thoughts of a genius. Instead, my mind wandered, I daydreamed, and I wondered idly about such
things as the complicated logistics of being Stephen Hawking.
That experience has intrigued me ever since. Similarly,
I’m intrigued by the not infrequent experience of listening to a talk or
reading a text of which, in the course of listening or reading, I believe I
have full understanding, only to discover, while describing the talk or the
text to someone, how partial my understanding really is. Regarding the
Hawking talk, I could recap a few ideas from the early part of the lecture
during conversations I joined in afterwards. Seven years later, I can’t recap
any of those ideas. Did I understand something of what I heard that day, and if
so, in what sense? Did I gain knowledge
of Stephen Hawking’s universe, or did I merely recognize ideas I had heard
before? And what to make of the pattern of my experience of understanding, from
smooth comprehension, to struggle, to floundering, to the near-complete
dispersion of my attention?
What did I know and when did I know it?
Can this uncertainty about the acquisition, retention, and
recapitulation of knowledge be resolved with reference to the properties of consciousness,
or more precisely, to aspects of attention?
Did my difficulty in understanding the Hawking lecture
reside in an attention deficit? Was it, in effect, a matter of my not having
heeded an internal instruction to pay
attention?
Of course not.
The insufficiency of the attention deficit explanation is
made clear by posing the question: What would best enable a listener to achieve
a state of near-complete attention while listening to Hawking lecture? The
question can be answered by listing the necessary prerequisites for optimal
attention:
· Relevant background knowledge/ memories
· Reliable cognitive
processes
· Extraordinary
intelligence/ high IQ
· Ability to identify
and appreciate new and novel patterns
Possessing the above attributes, a listener/ learner could
indeed pay attention to nearly every
word describing Stephen Hawking’s universe.
Attention, then, is conditional upon the possession of,
among other things, prior knowledge. Where does this prior knowledge come from?
What process of concept formation leads to our being able to think about and
comprehend a complex subject like cosmology?
What do we know and when do we know it?
It seems to me that what we know depends crucially upon the
time during which we know it. Knowing depends on memory. To help me clarify my
understanding of knowledge and memory, I turned to the Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy (a high-level handbook, the encyclopedia offered reassurance and
information, not unlike Calder’s Key).
Unsurprisingly, I was not the first to associate knowledge with memory. But it
turned out that most philosophers who had pondered memory in its relation to knowledge had done their pondering
before the modern era. Hence: “The twentieth century saw rather little work on
the epistemology of memory.” (Senor, Thomas D., Epistemological Problems of Memory, 2009, p. 12)
Senor notes the extent to which even our current conscious
knowledge depends on memory. Our ability to process an immediate impression
like ‘the sunset is beautiful’ depends on background knowledge, or background
memories, such as that we are looking west and that it is evening. While 20th
century philosophers gave little thought to memory’s contribution to knowledge,
researchers in psychology and cognitive science probed the function and role of
memory in numerous contexts. A current research project on concept
acquisition and short-term episodic memory describes the neural pathway
connecting knowledge to memory (Hassabis, Demis, Combining Systems Neuroscience and Machine Learning to Build AGI, Future of Humanity Institute,
2011). What about high-level abstract concepts like Time, and scientific
concepts like the Big Bang? In what ways might our understanding of these ideas
be associated with short- and long-term memory?
John Locke, in An
Essay Concerning Human Understanding, describes memory as a “storehouse” of
ideas. If I accept this metaphor, I might assume that the immediate issues
relevant to knowledge concern what ideas are present in the storehouse at any
given time, and how I access those ideas. Additionally, I might want to assume
a process of concept acquisition – a way of learning new ideas.
What kinds of ideas do we learn? Some of the abstract concepts we
learn very early on are perceptual and kinesthetic, like location and place. Later,
we acquire high-level abstract ideas like Right and Wrong. Bertrand Russell’s
concept of ideas in Analysis of Mind includes
ideas as images as well as ideas as propositions. (Senor, p. 6)
Although the 20th century produced little philosophical
thinking about knowledge and memory, epistemologists did develop the concept of
memory belief. Memory belief is the memory of an event or the memory of a
proposition about an event. Propositional memory might also be based on
something that is not an event: on reasoning and analysis. “The objects of
propositional memory are propositions; the objects of event memory are events.”
(Senor, p. 14) Thus high-level abstract concepts are part of dynamic processes such as analysis. Alas, modern philosophy of knowledge has more or less disintegrated the graphic "storehouse" metaphor; if knowledge is dynamic, it becomes less useful to think about concepts carefully stacked away in a repository.
What kinds of memory beliefs are involved in learning? Learning to read, a near-universal experience in the West, is a complex learning project spanning many years. Learning to read requires memory beliefs that are
propositional [background memories of the alphabet, phonics, spelling, the
decoding process, and semantics] and event-based [experiences over time of
being read to, reading aloud, decoding, subvocalizing, etc.] As human learners, we rely on our experiences in the world
as well as our reasoning to gain knowledge.
What happens when we transpose knowledge and memory into machine learning systems? Does the learning capacity of AI
come primarily from propositional memory beliefs? A proposition is an expression in language –
or signs – of something that can be believed, doubted, or denied or is either
true or false. In addition to computer learning systems' reliance on code, certain machines rely on a type of event-based
knowledge. These self-improving AI operate in such a way as to achieve their goals while
preserving their core utility functions (Omohundro, Stephen, The Nature of Self-Improving Artificial Intelligence, 2007) Self-improving AI
might acquire new information from experience and self-improve through access to their
source codes.
To our understanding of the limits of knowledge,
epistemologists have added the idea of the ambiguity response. (Steup, Matthias, Epistemology,
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2005, Section 5.6) The ambiguity
response asks whether, when I say I “know” something, I am referring to a
high-standards concept ({my} knowledge is infallible) or to a low-standards
concept ({my} knowledge is fallible). Even by the low-standards criterion, the
assertion that I “know” or “knew” Stephen Hawking’s ideas about Time and the
universe from listening to his talk is not credible.
Listening to Stephen Hawking talk about the universe, I
wondered if a little knowledge, while not a dangerous thing, might yet be
useful. On the assumption that my lack of comprehension was due in part to a
deficit in background knowledge and scientific thinking, I described my
trajectory from focus to dispersion to a computer scientist who had been in the
audience. The computer scientist promptly told me that his understanding of
Hawking had followed a similar trajectory, even though he had the necessary
background knowledge. It’s a reasonable assumption that, as a scientist, he was
also in possession of reliable cognitive processes and a high-functioning
intellect. He told me in fact that he had easily comprehended the first third
of the talk, struggled through the next third, and abandoned all hope in the
final third.
Did the computer scientist possess the gift of recognizing
novel patterns and appreciating their potential meaning? He told me about
reading A Brief History of Time. He
hadn’t written the book, but he could recount it. What did he know of the
universe, and when did he know it?
Bridging the chasm between Hawking’s original theory and my limited
grasp of it, the computer scientist knew enough at that moment to advance my understanding,
too.
No comments:
Post a Comment